The
Public Domain Revisited
Edward
Samuels·
This
is the "user-friendly" version,
but it may not be in sync with
the final version.
Cites or quotes should be to the final published version.
Loyola
of Los Angeles Law Review (Eldred symposium issue)
I. The Emergence of a
Theory of the Public Domain
A.
The Public Domain, Circa 1993
In a 1993 article published in the
Journal of the Copyright Society, I posed the following questions:
Is the public domain simply whatever is
left over after various tests of legal protection have been applied? Is it the
mere "background," the "negative" of whatever may be
protected? Or is there something about the public domain, some compelling
public policy or legal principle, that gives it a life of its own, that would
tend to attribute positive aspects to it, that would make it something of the
form instead of just the background?[1]
I
answered the questions as follows:
After
reviewing the various proposed arguments supporting a general theory of the
public domain . . . it would appear that there simply is no such general
theory. Instead, there are several discrete contexts in which arguments about
the public domain are encountered, each context raising different considerations
that may have little or nothing to do with each other, and that cumulatively
constitute what remains after one examines all possible sources of legal
protection for works of authorship. What is gained by reifying the negative,
and imagining a "theory" of the public domain? If one wants to
encourage a presumption against new forms or areas of protection, then one can
do so without having to invoke a magical "public domain." There are
dozens of battlegrounds between those who want to expand intellectual property
protection and those who want to limit it or narrow it in any given context.
The arguments in each context should be kept separate, since they raise
different policy issues.
Nevertheless,
the individual issues sometimes tend to be elusive, and one's attitude toward
them tends to be flavored as often as not by one's general attitude toward
copyright law. If those who find themselves continually on the side arguing for
a limitation of protection need a rallying cry, perhaps it can be "the public
domain." The invocation may seem to add a moral overtone to the argument,
to counterbalance the morally charged principles invoked time and again by the
protectionists. In the final analysis, however, [paraphrasing Ralph Brown]
"such vague rhetoric does little more than adorn the stage on which actual
choices must be played out."[2]
Prof. James Boyle has responded to the
questions I asked in my earlier article, as follows:
What is gained by reifying the negative?
Professor Samuels' question is a good one. He supplies part of the answer with
his thought that perhaps the language of the public domain will be used to
counter the language of sacred property. This is indeed an important point; language matters, and not just as
"rhetoric."
. . .
Of equal importance is the
power of a concept like the environment both to clarify and to reshape
perceptions of self interest.[3]
Prof.
Boyle goes on to compare the development of the "public domain"
movement to the development of the environmental law movement.
Notwithstanding the power of the word, or
the phrase, that Prof. Boyle describes, I believe that what I said in 1993 is
essentially still correct. The major difference is that the literature
invoking, creating, celebrating, or applying the "public domain"
ideology has expanded tremendously in the intervening years. Not since economic
theory invaded copyright (and just about every other area of law) have we seen
such a joining of voices to create a new body of scholarship, building one
article and book upon another—without having much actual influence, however,
upon the development of the law as created by legislators and judges. That last
point may be about to change. In their attack upon the copyright term extension
act, the petitioners in Eldred v.
Ashcroft[4] hope to
bring the public domain rhetoric and theory to the fore, and make it, from now
on, a dominant force in Congress's deliberations and judges' reviews of
copyright generally.
In my article, I identified six different
categories of the public domain. In each category, the trend over the past 200
years has been an expansion of copyright, and a concomitant diminution of what
might be considered the public domain. In the first category, the duration of
copyright has been extended from a maximum of 28 years to, under the Copyright
Term Extension Act of 1998, life of the author plus 70 years. The second
category, public domain through forfeiture of copyright, has been all but
eliminated by the abandonment of copyright formalities under the Berne
Implementation Act of 1988. The third category, works categorically excluded
from copyright, has also been diminishing over the years as the scope of
copyright has expanded to cover a widening category of works. I argued that the
other three categories, although aligned by some writers with public domain
theory, should particularly be decided on other grounds: public domain aspects
of otherwise copyrightable works, public domain as a substitute for preemption
analysis, and public domain as a substitute for measuring the retroactivity of
copyright enactments. In all six areas, the public domain advocates were making
arguments against the tide; they lamented the expansions of copyright, but
could hardly claim that the public domain analysis had in fact already worked
its way into dominant copyright theory.
B.
The Technological Battleground—Everybody's Losing!
In the intervening years, the public
domain agenda seems to have been spurred primarily by technological concerns.
What is fascinating to me is that, in the technological realm, everybody thinks
that they've lost the copyright battle. The copyright owners look on as others
digitize and disseminate their works on the Internet. In the words of Apple's
advertisements for its new iMac, the mantra is "Rip. Mix. Burn." This
sounds awfully like "Copy. Make a derivative work. Distribute." which
are supposed to be the exclusive rights of copyright under section 106. The
copyright owners are horrified at the "hemorrhaging" of their control
over their works.
Some of the early technological
pronouncements had a decidedly flippant tone, as if no one but the digerati
could possibly understand what was going on. As declared in Wired Magazine in March 1994, and
repeated by such advocates as Mitch Kapor and John Perry Barlow in presentations
across the country,
Notions of property, value, ownership,
and the nature of wealth itself are changing more fundamentally than at any
time since the Sumerians first poked cuneiform into wet clay and called it
stored grain. Only a very few people are aware of the enormity of this shift,
and fewer of them are lawyers or public officials.
This
was the same time as Internet gurus were proclaiming that the Internet world
was not subject to other basic concepts, like principles of investment,
accounting or gravity.
However, the established interests
did in fact "get it." Various copyright industries were successful in
convincing Congress to pass copyright laws directed at the new digitization of
copyrighted works. The Record Rental Amendment of 1984 created an exception to
the first sale doctrine in the case of rented audio works, largely because the
emergence of DVDs made the copying of rented music much more of a threat to the
existing markets for distribution of music.[5]
The Computer Rental Software Amendment of 1990 created a similar exception for
the rental of computer software.[6]
Congress passed the Audio Home Recording Act of 1992[7]
to handle the modern consequences of home recording using the new digital
recording devices. Congress passed the Digital Performance Rights in Sound
Recordings Act of 1995[8]
to handle the distribution of music over the Internet and other digital
distribution systems. And then, in 1998, Congress adopted the Digital
Millennium Copyright Act[9]
to allow copyright owners to better enforce their rights through technological
protection measures and copyright management information systems.
The landscape has so changed that
the public domain advocates are beginning to announce that they, not the copyright industries, are losing the copyright
battle. The primary spokesperson, Lawrence Lessig, in his most recent
manifesto,[10] portrays a
grim future—actually present—in which the digital technologies aren't a
liberating force for the masses, but rather a tool of the copyright industries
in absolutely controlling access to cultural works.[11]
It all comes as something of a surprise to the copyright industries that they
have won the war.
Given the recent technological
battleground, it is interesting, and perhaps surprising, that the major case to
present the public domain agenda before the Supreme Court should have nothing
to do with technology. Instead, it ostensibly focuses upon just about the
oldest question that has been at the heart of the copyright debate from the
beginning—how long should the term of copyright be? As I'll discuss later,
there is probably a tendency to try to view the public domain agenda broadly,
and decide even the age-old questions in light of the new issues raised by
technology. As I'll suggest, it is better for everyone if we focus upon the
issues one at a time, and if we don't allow the broader agenda to cloud
decisions that must be made in the discrete contexts.
C.
The Relationship Between Public Domain Analysis and Other Bases of Copyright
In my 1993 article, I briefly explored
the relationship between the discussions of the public domain and basic
theories about the role and basis for copyright, as follows:
The writings about the importance of the
public domain seem to some extent to parallel other arguments that have been
around since copyright was first recognized in English and American law;
namely, arguments about the theoretical source or justification for copyright
generally. Many protectionists have tried to justify copyright law as based
upon (1) natural rights, (2) moral rights or (3) property rights. Critics have
tried to limit this approach by (1) gleefully citing the embarrassing early
history of copyright law in England . . . ;(2) emphasizing the "social
utility" theory of copyright, by which the only or main justification for
allowing what is basically a "monopoly" is the ultimate good that is
achieved for society by an increase in the number, maybe even the quality, of
works destined for the public domain; and (3) in recent years, subjecting
copyright protection to a strict economic analysis that would limit any benefit
to the copyright owner that was not clearly justified by a concomitant increase
in the public good (read "public domain"). These arguments might be
bolstered by (4) an explicit or implicit reference to principles, even
constitutional standards, from outside the copyright clause, particularly the
first amendment's guarantee of free speech.[12]
The arguments about the public domain,
and the theoretical underpinnings of copyright, have taken on almost a
religious fervor in recent years. Otherwise reasonable people arguing different
sides of the issue tend to become as emotionally overwrought as any abortion
rights (or anti-abortion rights) advocate. In several recent conferences and
private discussions about copyright theory, about all one has to do is mention
the words "natural rights" or "property rights," and public
domain advocates are practically jumping from their seats to "set the
record straight." They argue passionately that property rights talk is a
development of the latter part of the twentieth century, that copyright wasn't
brought under the rubric of "intellectual property" until the last
fifty years when the giant corporations somehow manipulated the world into
thinking that their exclusive rights of patent, copyright, trademark and other
rights were entitled to be protected as "property."[13]
But the natural rights and property
rights rhetoric is firmly rooted in copyright history. It is recognized as the
basis for copyright protection in civil law and other countries outside of
England and the United States.[14]
Although it is commonly argued that the English and United States origins were
based upon non-property, non-natural rights principles, the preambles to
several of the state copyright statutes under the Articles of Confederation
incorporated property and natural rights rhetoric with the "social
utility" theory. For example, the Connecticut statute of 1783, which
served as the model for the Georgia and New York statutes, began:
Whereas
it is perfectly agreeable to the principles of natural equity and justice, that
every author should be secured in receiving the profits that may arise from the
sale of his works, and such security may encourage men of learning and genius
to publish their writings; which may do honor and service to mankind . . .[15]
The Massachusetts statute of 1783,
which served as a model for the New Hampshire and Rhode Island statutes,
provided:
Whereas the improvement of
knowledge, the progress of civilization, the public weal of the community, and
the advancement of human happiness, greatly depend on the efforts of learned
and ingenious persons in the various arts and sciences: As the principal
encouragement such persons can have to make great and beneficial exertions of
this nature, must exist in the legal security of the fruits of their study and
industry to themselves; and as such security is one of the natural rights of
all men, there being no property more peculiarly a man's own than that which is
produced by the labour of his mind . . .[16]
The North Carolina statute of 1785
provided:
Whereas nothing is more
strictly a man's own than the fruit of his study, and it is proper that men
should be encouraged to pursue useful knowledge by the hope of reward; and as
the security of literary property must greatly tend to encourage genius, to promote
useful discoveries, and to the general extension of arts and commerce . . .[17]
In addition, many scholars and observers
over the years have found natural and property rights bases in United States
copyright legislation. For example, the Report of the Register of Copyrights,
in the early stages of copyright revision, identified strands of property right
and personal right, as well as monopoly limitation theories.[18]
Many of the expansions and other
developments of copyright simply can't be explained by a strict "public
domain" theory of copyright. As concluded by Paul Goldstein, “The 1976
Copyright Act’s special treatment of involuntary transfers of copyright, for
example, and its provisions for termination of transfers can be better
explained in terms of natural rights theory than in terms of a utilitarian
balance of social benefit.”[19]
Contrary to the suggestions of some public domain advocates, Goldstein
concludes: "As a general rule, copyright law in the United States entitles
copyright owners to capture the full value that consumers attach to their works
and not just the minimum sum that they would require to support their
investment."[20]
Here's my conclusion as expressed in the
1993 article:
American copyright law has suffered for
two hundred years from the absence of a clearly articulated theoretical basis.
Some might see this as some sort of oversight or conspiracy. I don't think so.
I think that Congress and the courts have thereby maintained flexibility in the
development of the law.
. . . [T]he different
theories represent different ways of looking at copyright law that can be used
to explain different aspects of it, but none of which is adequate to explain
the whole, and none of which trumps the others.
I
even suggested that, based upon the clear expansions of copyright over the
years, and the "convergence" of copyright principles through the
adoption of international standards, "It should therefore be possible to
ascribe to American copyright law the broad theoretical basis that until recent
years may have been premature."[21]
In any event, because there is no
consensus that any one copyright principle trumps any other, and because the
whole of copyright is ultimately based upon a balancing of interests, the
principles simply don't help in resolving discrete copyright issues. If it were
within my power, I would call a truce. I wouldn't invoke "natural
rights" and "property rights" justifications for copyright, if
public domain advocates would concede that there is no "public
domain" theory that trumps other rights. We could then proceed to deal
with the copyright issues as they arise.
D.
"Retroactivity"
In my earlier article, I argued that
the public domain rhetoric was sometimes used, inappropriately, as a substitute
for measuring the retroactivity of a copyright statute. After analyzing the
issue, I concluded as follows:
[I]t is simply not clear whether Congress
is prohibited from reviving works that previously entered the public domain,
and there are at least some convincing suggestions that it has power to revive
works not previously protected. In any event, issues of retroactivity should
not be determined by an ill-defined concept of the "public domain,"
but can be analyzed by reference to a richer literature dealing with
retroactivity of legislation.[22]
Part
of that "richer literature" suggests that
Even for statutes that affect criminal
behavior or contract rights, most securely protected against retroactive
legislation by the due process, ex post facto, and impairment of contracts
clauses of the Constitution, it is hard to make absolute statements.[23]
As stated by one expert in statutory
construction,
It is misleading to use the terms
"retrospective" and "retroactive," as has sometimes been
done, to mean that the act is unconstitutional. The question of validity rests
on further subtle judgments concerning the fairness of applying the new
statute. Even where a constitution explicitly and unqualifiedly prohibits the
enactment of retrospective statutes, the courts usually strike down only those
statutes whose retroactivity results in measurable unfairness.[24]
Since I made my observations, Congress
has indeed found a context in which it has restored copyrights in certain
works. Congress passed a new section 104A, which provided for the restoration
of foreign copyrights that had gone into the public domain, primarily through
noncompliance with U.S. copyright formalities.[25]
That amendment was passed pursuant to international obligations—first, in 1993,
in the North American Free Trade Agreement, and then, in 1994, broadened as a
result of the World Trade Organization agreement. Public domain advocates have
brought a court challenge to that act in the case of Golan v. Ashcroft.[26]
Section 104A was designed partly to be fair to foreign
authors, whose works went into the public domain in this country through a
failure to comply with formalities that no other country required. It was also
motivated by a desire to allow U.S. copyright owners to get their works
"restored" in other countries that for one reason or another[27]
hadn't granted copyright protection.
It is not my purpose to defend the Golan case or section 104A here. The Eldred case that is the subject of the
rest of this article does not actually involve the retroactive application of
copyright law, since the 1998 Copyright Term Extension Act that is challenged
in that case doesn't apply to any works that had already fallen into the public
domain. And, as I urge here, we shouldn't be arguing the Eldred case by jockeying for position in other contexts. But I do
believe that my cautious approach, not necessarily setting off the
constitutional alarm every time a magic word, like "retroactive,"[28]
is used, is as important today as it was when I made the suggestion a decade
ago. Let's save the arguments about Golan
for another day.
II. Eldred v. Reno/Ashcroft
A.
The Undesirable Extremes
1. The
D.C. Circuit Opinion
In 1998, Congress passed the
Copyright Term Extension Act (hereinafter "the CTEA"). That act
extended the term of protection for all works created after January 1, 1978
(the effective date of the Copyright Act of 1976) by 20 years, from life of the
author plus 50 years to life of the author plus 70 years. It extended the term
of works created prior to 1978 from 75 years from publication to 95 years from
publication. Eric Eldred and various other plaintiffs, represented by Lawrence
Lessig, brought a constitutional challenge to the CTEA, suing Janet Reno, as
Attorney General, in the District Court of the District of Columbia. That court
upheld the constitutionality of the CTEA. In 2001, the District of Columbia
Circuit Court of Appeals affirmed the lower court, with a dissent by Judge
Sentelle. The Circuit Court denied a petition for rehearing and for rehearing
en banc. The Supreme Court granted a writ of certiorari in February 2002.
The approach of the D.C. Circuit
Court was to cut off discussion of the constitutional issues by the adoption of
what appeared to be an absolute rule that copyright laws were immune from
constitutional attack. The court concluded that the preamble to the
Constitution's copyright clause (granting Congress the power "To promote
the Progress of Science and useful Arts," by securing exclusive rights
"for limited Times") "is not a substantive limit on Congress'
legislative power." The court went on to conclude that "copyrights
are categorically immune from challenges under the First Amendment"
because of the idea/expression dichotomy, the fair use doctrine, and other
limiting principles that already factor in the constitutional considerations.
The concern of public domain
scholars is not only with copyright term extension, but with other recent
expansions of copyright. For example, as discussed above, the public domain
advocates have brought a lawsuit challenging the restoration of copyright under
section 104A of the copyright act. But the 800-pound gorilla looming on the
horizon is the Digital Millennium Copyright Act of 1998 ("the DMCA").
That act provided for the legal protection of technological protection systems
and copyright management information systems. In Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Reimerdes,[29]
the district court for the Southern District of New York, and then, under the
name Universal City Studios, Inc. v.
Corley,[30] the Second
Circuit Court of Appeals upheld the statute against constitutional challenge.
Despite the ruling of the Second Circuit Court of Appeals, some scholars still
maintain that the statute is constitutionally defective because, as the courts
have interpreted it, the act does not apply the idea/expression dichotomy, the
fair use doctrine, or other limitations of copyright to the DMCA protections.
Constitutional issues might also be relevant to other acts that Congress may
consider, such as in the area of database protection.
The public domain scholars are thus
particularly alarmed at the categorical exclusion test adopted by the D.C.
Circuit Court in Eldred. Quite
frankly, the petitioners should also have been alarmed, since the broadness of
the ruling may have been what piqued the interest of the Supreme Court in
granting certiorari. The petitioners were able to frame the issue as whether
the D.C. Circuit erred in holding that copyrights are "categorically
immune from challenge under the First Amendment." The respondent now has
to make the tactical decision: to what extent should he box himself into the
corner of defending the categorical test announced by the Circuit Court; or, at
least for the sake of argument, concede a potential First Amendment claim, and
jump right into the merits of the case? Presumably, respondent will address the
First Amendment arguments on the merits.
I am sure that, had the D.C. Circuit
Court's analysis been the final statement on the matter, future courts, when
faced with challenges to other Congressional actions, would have been able to
limit the Eldred holding to the facts
of the case. No matter what the court said about categorical exclusions,
different situations raise different concerns, and those concerns should be
separately addressed in the context of each case. Since the case will now be
decided by the Supreme Court, that Court should weigh the copyright and First
Amendment policies in more detail, instead of relying upon a categorical
approach.
2. Petitioners' Novel Theory
Petitioners' argument is based upon
the premise that the CTEA violates the "limited Times" provision of
the copyright clause. Presumably recognizing that the life of the author plus
70 years, or 95 years, is obviously a "limited time," they seek to
link the limited times provision to a novel interpretation of the copyright
clause. They essentially argue that the phrase "to promote the Progress of
Science and useful Arts" is synonymous with an increase in the public
domain. They argue that Congress may not decrease the public domain (an issue
not before the Court in this case, since the CTEA did not remove a single work
from the public domain). Extending their novel theory, they argue that once Congress,
pursuant to its constitutional power, has set a term of copyright, it is
prohibited from extending that term, even if the term has not yet expired.[31]
The gist of petitioners' reasoning
is that Congress may only grant rights when to do so will result in the
creation of new works. Once a work has been created, under whatever inducement
existed at the time of its creation, Congress may not grant any further rights
to the copyright owners, since to do so would be to grant rights without the
"quid pro quo" called for under the Constitution—the creation of new
works.
If the D.C. Circuit opinion was
objectionable because it was overly broad, the petitioners' theory is even more
objectionable. If the Court were to adopt the petitioners' reasoning, not only
would it decide the instant case, but it would have implications in dozens of
other settings. I will respond to the petitioners' argument in the next
section. But let's take a look now at the "parade of horribles" (or,
from petitioners' view, perhaps a "parade of desirables") that might
flow from an adoption of their novel theory.
If the 1998 term extension is
unconstitutional, then presumably the 1994 addition of section 104A, restoring
copyright in foreign works that had already gone into the public domain, would
also be unconstitutional. If that is the case, then the United States would be
in violation of our treaty obligations under NAFTA and WTO, and there would be
serious international repercussions.
If Congress may not extend the term
of existing copyrights, as petitioners argue, then the 1976 extension of
copyright to life of the author plus 50 years was also unconstitutional. If the
1976 extension is unconstitutional, then we are in violation of the Berne
Treaty, with serious international repercussions.
Works used to go into the public
domain whenever they failed to comply with the copyright formalities of notice,
registration, and renewal. Does that mean that it was unconstitutional in 1988
to dispense with copyright formalities?[32]
Was it unconstitutional to "rescue" works from going into the public
domain when Congress, in 1992, provided for automatic renewal of works
published after 1964?[33]
Was it unconstitutional for Congress to expand the scope of rights in
copyrighted works, as it has done many times in the 212 year history of
copyright? Was it unconstitutional when Congress passed the DMCA, granting new
rights in technological protections systems and copyright management systems,
even for works that already existed?
Petitioners might be delighted at
any of the above suggestions. But the promotion of science and useful arts is
allied with, not opposed to, the interests of copyright owners. As stated by
James Madison in The Federalist No. 43, "the public good fully coincides .
. . with the claims of individuals." As explained by Justice O'Connor in
the Harper & Row case, "It
should not be forgotten that the Framers intended copyright itself to be the
engine of free expression. By establishing a marketable right to the use of
one's expression, copyright supplies the economic incentive to create and
disseminate ideas . . ."[34]
Would it therefore be unconstitutional for Congress to decrease the rights of copyright, affecting the rights in existing
works, as it did, for example, in the so-called "Fairness in Music
Licensing Act" of 1998?[35]
The problem with petitioners'
argument is that it would not only decide the instant case, but it would also
frame the issue in practically every other area of copyright. Petitioners argue
that the categorical approach of the D.C. Circuit is unacceptable because the
court identified no "stopping point" by which to measure what was
constitutional.[36] The
petitioners' own argument is unacceptable because it, too, has no
"stopping point." It would bar Congress from making any adjustments in the terms of existing
copyrights.
The Supreme Court should therefore
not endorse either the categorical approach of the D.C. Circuit, nor the novel
theory of the petitioners. If it affirms the D.C. Circuit, as I believe it
should, then it should make clear that the decision is based upon a full
consideration of the First Amendment standards, and that courts are not
foreclosed in other contexts from considering limitations that may be raised by
the preamble to the copyright clause and by the First Amendment. If it should
choose to reverse the D.C. Circuit, and either remand the case or make a
finding on the merits, then it should make clear that it is deciding only the
issue of Congress's power to set the duration of copyright. It should not adopt
any particular "theory" of copyright that will have an impact on
cases beyond the one argued before it.
B.
The History of the Constitutional Phrase "to promote the Progress of
Science and useful Arts."
As
stated in the previous section, the petitioners' argument rests upon the
premise that the constitutional phrase "to promote the Progress of Science
and useful Arts" is synonymous with placing works into the public domain.
In my amicus brief filed with the Supreme Court, I review the history of the
constitutional phrase "to promote the Progress of Science and useful
Arts," and demonstrate that the phrase incorporates many factors, not just
an increase in the public domain. To focus upon just the one factor is to
thwart the meaning of the constitutional phrase, and to bind Congress in ways
inconsistent with the full meaning of the constitutional mandate. Here are the
arguments I make in the brief.
1.
The Constitutional Phrase "the Progress of Science and useful Arts"
Is Not Directed Primarily at the Ultimate Increase in the Public Domain.
a.
The State Statutes under the Articles of Confederation.
There is little direct record of
what the drafters of the Constitution intended when they adopted the phrase
"to promote the Progress of Science and useful Arts." But much
insight can be gleaned from the practice of the states under the Articles of
Confederation, since it can be assumed that the drafters of the Constitution
and of the first copyright act were familiar with the pre-existing state laws.
As seen earlier, the preambles to
the state statutes contained language of "natural rights" and
"property rights." The preambles also made clear that the inducement
contemplated in the statutes was to "encourage learned and ingenious
persons to write" (as stated in the Massachusetts and related statutes)
and to "encourage men of learning and genius to publish" (as stated
in the Connecticut and related statutes) their works. Although works were
obviously intended to go into the public domain at the expiration of the
copyrights, the "public good" wasn't something that would be achieved
only at that later date; the "public good" was achieved at the outset
by the creation and publication of the works.
b. The Constitutional Phrase.
The Constitution grants Congress the
power to pass copyright law as follows:
Article I, sec. 8. The Congress shall
have Power: . . .
To promote the Progress of Science and
useful Arts, by securing, for limited Times, to Authors and Inventors, the
exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.
In
The Federalist No. 43, James Madison gave pretty much the only contemporary
public explanation of the phrase when he said:
The utility of this power will scarcely
be questioned. The copyright of authors has been solemnly adjudged, in Great
Britain, to be a right of common law. . . .
The public good fully coincides . . . with the claims of individuals.
The States cannot separately make effectual provision [for copyright], and most
of them have anticipated the decision of this point, by laws passed at the
instance of Congress.[37]
By "the public good,"
Madison could not have meant simply "the public domain," since the
"public good" will not "fully coincide . . . with the claims of
individuals" after the term of copyright has expired. What he meant was
that the progress of science and arts depends entirely upon the creation and
distribution of such works. Madison's focus was, as the Constitution's focus
was, as the earlier state statutes' focus was, primarily on the creation and
distribution of works. Of course, it was assumed that works would ultimately go
into the public domain, but that was as a result of the "limited
Times" provision, not something necessarily envisioned within the
"Progress of Science and useful Arts" clause.
c. The Plain Meaning and Logical
Understanding of the Constitutional Phrase
The copyright clause of the
Constitution is the only enumerated power within Article 1, section 8, that
mentions the "purpose" for which it was enacted. Why might the
framers have chosen to add that language, instead of empowering Congress to grant
exclusive rights to authors and inventors without limitation? Possibly, the
framers were simply following the pattern of the prior state enactments, almost
all of which had preambles explaining their purpose. The "whereas"
clauses in the preambles explained the purposes of the earlier statutes, but
they can hardly be read as specific limitations upon the rights granted under
those statutes.
The other model for the structure of
the constitutional phrase was the Statute of Anne, adopted in England in 1710.[38]
That act was entitled "An Act for the Encouragement of Learning, by
vesting the Copies of Printed Books in the Authors or Purchasers of such
Copies, during the Times therein mentioned." It is hard to imagine how the
words "Encouragement of Learning" provided any particular limitation
upon what rights were granted.
Petitioners would have us believe
that "Science and useful Arts" does not progress until someone, such
as petitioner Eldred, has made a work available to the public free of
charge. But that certainly isn't the
common sense meaning of "Progress of Science and useful Arts."
Millions of works are created, published, read, and commented upon every year.
Some of the greatest works receive accolades and criticism, and literary and
other awards, shortly after their publication, for the contribution that they
make to the arts and sciences. For example, the Nobel Prizes are awarded to
those who "shall have conferred the greatest benefit on mankind."
Under the Nobel rules, "To be eligible to be considered for a prize, a
written work shall have been issued in print or have been published in another
form."[39] Pulitzer
Prizes are awarded for "work done" and "published" or
"performed" during the prior year. The public value of the works is
hardly diminished by the fact that they will not go into the public domain for
many years.
Authors who make
"transformative" uses of copyrighted works should and do have wide
leeway to produce their works under the fair use doctrine, as illustrated by
the Supreme Court's decision in Campbell
v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc.,[40]
and the Eleventh Circuit's decision in Suntrust
Bank v. Houghton Mifflin Co.[41] Petitioners, however, are not such
"creators" who desire to make transformative uses of existing works;
instead, their businesses, for the most part, are in making already existing
works available over the Internet or otherwise. While this may be a valuable
service to the public, it does not result in any immediate "Progress"
of "Science and useful Arts," since the works that they distribute
are works that have already been published, almost all of which are already
available (though of course for a fee) from other sources.
In short, the "Progress of
Science and useful Arts" takes place primarily when works are created and
published, not (or at least not primarily) when they go into the public domain.
2. United States Copyright Statutes
a. The Copyright Act of 1790
The first copyright act, passed in
1790 in the first Congress, was entitled "An Act for the encouragement of
learning, by securing the copies of maps, charts, and books, to the authors and
proprietors of such copies, during the times therein mentioned." The
legislative history of the act confirms that Congress, in passing the act, was
focusing upon the inducement to create and publish. President George
Washington, in his January 1790 address to a joint session of Congress, urged
the new Congress that "there is nothing which can better deserve your
patronage than the promotion of science and literature." He went on:
"Whether this desirable object [knowledge] will be best promoted by
affording aids to seminaries of learning already established, by the institution
of a national university, or by any other expedients, will be well worthy of a
place in the deliberations of the legislature."[42]
Congress responded with an address to the president: "We concur with you
in the sentiment that . . . the promotion of science and literature will
contribute to the security of a free Government; in the progress of our
deliberations we shall not lose sight of objects so worthy of our regard."[43]
The act that was passed by Congress and signed into law by President Washington
in that same year was the copyright act, entitled "An Act for the
encouragement of learning."
The 1790 copyright act was
inconsistent with petitioners' theory that Congress may not constitutionally
extend the duration of existing works. Most states already had copyright laws
that created exclusive rights for periods varying from a minimum of 14 to a
maximum of 28 years.[44]
The 1790 act not only continued these copyrights in force, but extended the
duration to run for a period of 14 to (upon renewal) 28 years from the date of
new registration. This was not some incidental effect, but was quite clearly
set forth in the statute in a separate provision:
Be
it enacted . . . That from and after the passing of this act, the author and
authors of any map, chart, book or books already printed within these United
States . . . shall have the sole right and liberty of printing, reprinting,
publishing and vending such map, chart, book or books, for the term of fourteen
years from the recording that title thereof in the clerk's office . . .[45]
Thus,
the authors of existing works, even if they had already received up to seven
years of protection under the prior state laws (from 1783 to 1790), or even if
their works might have gone into the public domain because they were from a
state that hadn’t yet passed an effective copyright law, were entitled to begin
their copyrights anew under the 1790 statute.
b. Subsequent Extensions
All subsequent copyright acts that
have extended the term of copyright—to a total of 42 years from the date of
publication in 1831,[46]
56 years from publication in 1909,[47]
life of the author plus 50 years in 1978, and life of the author plus 70 years
in 1998—have specifically applied the extension to existing works. This
application of new terms to existing works was not some incidental outcome, but
was specifically considered by Congress.
In
1831, when the first term of copyright was extended to 28 years, to create a
maximum copyright term of 42 years, this result was accomplished by repealing
the prior act, but preserving rights under that act and applying the terms of
the new act to the existing works.
Sec. 14. And be it further enacted, That the "Act for the encouragement
of learning, by securing the copies of maps, charts, and books, to the authors
and proprietors of such copies during the times therein mentioned," passed
May thirty-first, one thousand seven hundred and ninety, and the act
supplementary thereto . . . shall be, and the same are hereby, repealed:
saving, always, such rights as may have been obtained in conformity to their
provisions.
Sec. 15 And be it further enacted, That all and several the provisions of
this act, intended for the protection and security of copyrights, and providing
remedies, penalties, and forfeitures . . . shall be held and construed to
extend to the benefit of the legal proprietor or proprietors of each and every
copyright heretofore obtained, according to law, during the term thereof, in
the same manner as if such copyright had been entered and secured according to
the directions of this act.
The
1909 act, extending the renewal term of copyright by an additional 14 years,
for a total copyright term of up to 56 years, made clear that it did not revive
works that had already gone into the public domain; but the extension of the
additional 14 years did apply to
copyrights that had been obtained under the prior act and had not yet expired.
Section 8. Copyright not to subsist in
works in public domain, or published prior to July 1, 1909, and not already
copyrighted . . .
No copyright shall subsist in the
original text of any work which is in the public domain, or in any work which
was published in this country or any foreign country prior to July 1, 1909, and
has not been already copyrighted in the United States . . .
In the 20 years of legislative
history leading up to the 1976 Act, Congress carefully considered the varying
means for measuring the term of copyright. Although it adopted the life plus 50
year term for works created after the effective date of the statute, Congress
chose to continue to measure the term of existing copyrights (and
works-for-hire and pseudonymous and anonymous works) from the date of
publication.[48]
Under the 1976 Act, life plus 50
years actually resulted in a shorter
duration of copyright for works produced toward the end of an author’s life.
Such works would be protected for a little over 50 years, less than the 56-year
maximum under the 1909 law. Congress concluded that, on average, the life of the author plus 50 years was the equivalent
of about 75 years from publication; but, of course, in individual instances, it
might be more or less. That’s the inevitable result of using two different
methods for computing the duration of copyright.
Congress considered that it might be
unfair to grant the benefits of the 19-year term extension to licensees who may
have paid only for a shorter license term; accordingly, Congress established in
section 304(c) an elaborate provision for "termination," or
recapture, of the extension term for the benefit of the authors or their heirs.
In this way, the term extension was not necessarily a "victory" for
the large corporations that may have owned many of the copyrights, since in
many cases they had to renegotiate the rights with the original authors or
their heirs.
While Congress in 1976 extended the
term of copyright for works that had already been published, it significantly
decreased the term of protection for works that were not yet published. Under
prior law from 1790 through 1977, state common law copyright in unpublished works had extended in
perpetuity. Under the new act, Congress brought works under the federal system
of copyright beginning from the date of “fixation” in a “tangible medium of
expression” (rather than from the date of publication) and preempted state common
law copyright in unpublished works. In section 303, Congress provided that
copyright in previously created but unpublished works would be measured by the
life plus 50 year term. However, in order to prevent “old” unpublished works
from immediately going into the public domain, Congress provided that no such
works would go into the public domain before December 31, 2002, at the
earliest; and, to encourage publication of such “old” works, Congress provided
that if such “old” works were published by the end of the year 2002, they would
be granted additional protection until the year 2027. In any event, since the
duration of copyright for unpublished works was reduced from “in perpetuity,”
and since some copyrights actually received a shorter term of copyright under the new Act, the net effect of the
1976 Act was not simply to “extend” the term of copyright, but more precisely
to “adjust” the term of copyright.
While Congress's prior enactments of
course do not definitively decide the constitutional issue in the case, they do
evince a practice of careful deliberation that has been clear and consistent
from the first copyright act of 1790 to the copyright act of 1998. Each of
these statutes, affecting the terms of existing as well as future copyrights,
is inconsistent with the novel constitutional theory proposed by petitioners.
c. Other Copyright Acts
Extension of the copyright term is
not the only way in which Congress has expanded the scope of copyright over the
years. To give just a few examples, owners of previously copyrighted works saw
their rights expand when Congress added the right to receive payment under a
compulsory licensing system for cable retransmissions in 1976;[49]
a public display right in 1976;[50]
certain moral rights in 1990;[51]
and digital performance rights in sound recordings in 1992.[52]
Such additional rights could not possibly represent an incentive to the
original copyright owners to create their works; and so, by petitioners' logic,
Congress should never have been able to add to the rights in such works already
in existence. Yet it is absurd to assume that Congress does not have the power
to make periodic adjustments to the scope of existing copyrights.
Congress has "decreased"
the public domain (in the sense that it has passed laws slowing the rate at
which works go into the public domain) in many other ways besides the extension
of the copyright term. For example, many more works traditionally went into the
public domain as a result of failure to use the copyright notice, failure to
register, or failure to renew, than have gone into the public domain because of
expiration of copyright. (If, as petitioners assert in their brief, only 15% of
copyrighted works were generally renewed, then 85% of the works went into the
public domain when they were not renewed.) When Congress in 1988 eliminated the
copyright notice and registration requirements as part of its obligations under
the Berne Convention,[53]
and when in 1992 it provided for automatic renewal of copyrights still in their
first terms, it "rescued" many more existing works from going into
the public domain than it did when it passed the CTEA. Again, by petitioners'
logic, these "assaults" on the public domain should never have been
allowed. The fact that Congress has continually readjusted not only the term of
copyright, but also the scope of rights in existing copyrights, and has
abandoned the requirement of formalities, also for existing copyrights,
demonstrates that Congress simply is not limited in the novel way suggested by
petitioners.
3.
The "Progress of Science and useful Arts" Involves Dozens of
Considerations Beyond Merely the Devolution of Copyrighted Works into the
Public Domain.
a. International Considerations
One of the major accomplishments in
U.S. copyright in the latter part of the twentieth century was the
internationalization of copyright standards, prompted to a large extent by the
internationalization of trade and technology. The 1790 act had protected only
U.S. authors. It was not until 1891 that foreign authors were granted at least
some minimal level of protection, though that protection, because of copyright
formalities, was often more illusory than real. In 1952, the United States was
instrumental in convincing much of the world to adopt the Universal Copyright
Convention, which allowed a U.S.-inspired international copyright system to
exist alongside the Berne convention that governed most of the rest of the
world. The situation was an embarrassment within the international copyright
community, and undermined the ability of U.S. trade negotiators to encourage
other countries to enhance their copyright protection of foreign—including
U.S.—books, music, movies, and computer programs. Finally, in 1988, the United
States joined the rest of the world by adhering to the Berne Convention.[54]
The Berne Convention provides that
all member countries must protect copyright for a minimum term of life of the
author plus 50 years,[55]
and eliminate all formalities as prerequisites to copyright.[56]
The extension of copyright to life plus 50 years, as provided in the major
overhaul of U.S. copyright law in 1976, and the elimination of formalities in
the Berne Implementation Act of 1988, were therefore absolute prerequisites to
U.S. adherence to Berne.
Not only does Berne require a term
of life of the author plus 50 years, but it also requires that member countries
grant that term to all works that have not already gone into the public domain
in a particular country. As provided in Article 18(1): “This Convention shall
apply to all works which, at the moment of its coming into force, have not yet
fallen into the public domain in the country of origin through the expiry of
the term of protection.” Thus, the term extension for existing works still
under copyright protection was an absolute necessity for joining Berne under
Article 18(1).[57]
The 1998 extension, from life of the
author plus 50 years to life of the author plus 70 years, was not required
under our international obligations. However, it was designed to match the term
of copyright recently adopted throughout the European Union and by other
countries. Under Article 7(8) of the Berne Convention, countries with the life
plus 70 year term do not have to recognize the rights of foreign authors whose
works have expired in their own countries.
Since the United States is a net
exporter of copyrighted works, it certainly made sense for the United States to
grant the longer term, and thereby allow U.S. authors to take advantage of the
longer term available abroad. And, since the United States was simply matching
the longer term available in other countries, it is not likely that Congress,
absent the strong international considerations, will extend the U.S. term of
copyright yet again. Petitioners’ suggestion that Congress will continue to
grant further extensions whenever the copyright industries ask for them is
simply not a likely scenario.
The petitioners suggest that the
drafters of the Constitution would be horrified at a term of life plus 70
years, or 95 years for existing works. In 1790, the term of copyright adopted
by Congress matched the British, and what would become the international,
standard of the day. Would the framers of the Constitution be shocked to learn
that Congress had, over the years, extended the term of copyright to match the
expanding international norm? It is more likely that they would be shocked if we had not done so. Were Madison to view
the state of international trade and technology today, he might well conclude,
as he did about the individual state statutes in 1790, that one country “cannot
separately make effectual provision” for copyright, and that most countries
today have “anticipated the decision of this point” by passing laws in
conformity with international standards.[58]
b.
Other Considerations
While the exact contours of the
"Progress of Science and useful Arts" are not clear, many of the
major theories and limitations of copyright adopted over the years do in fact,
and were intended to, promote such progress.
For example, the Supreme Court has
noted the “First Amendment protections already embodied in the Copyright Act’s
distinction between copyrightable expression and uncopyrightable facts and
ideas, and the latitude for scholarship and comment traditionally afforded by
fair use.”[59] Works of
utility[60]
are not covered by copyright, but are free for the taking. The first sale
doctrine,[61] the
numerous compulsory licenses, the limitations in section 110 protecting various
performances, and the exclusion of protection for government works[62]
all carve out major limitations that promote the progress of science and arts.
The limitation of copyright protection to “original works of authorship,”[63]
the special rules for library photocopying,[64]
the many definitional limitations in section 101, and the fact that copyright
doesn’t prevent all uses of copyrighted works, but only those enumerated in the
exclusive rights sections 106 and 106A, all in their own way foster the
"Progress of Science and useful Arts." There is hardly a principle of
copyright that does not reflect a careful balance between the rights of
copyright owners and copyright users. It is presumably precisely because the
balance is so intricate and delicate that the framers of the Constitution
assigned to Congress the task of setting copyright policy.
c. The CTEA.
In enacting the CTEA, Congress again
gave careful consideration to balancing the interests of copyright owners and
copyright users. For example, Congress coupled copyright term extension with
the so-called “Fairness in Music Licensing Act,” which, in amending sections
110(5) and 513, put severe limitations on the enforcement of public performance
rights by music copyright holders. Responding to the concerns raised by library
representatives, Congress added a new subsection 108(h), which provides for an
expanded library exemption for the reproduction of copyrighted works during the
last 20 years added by the act.
As explained at p. __, supra, “old” unpublished works were
slated to go into the public domain after December 31, 2002. As originally
proposed, the CTEA would have extended the protection of such works by an extra
ten years.[65] Responding
to the concerns raised in the committee hearings, however, Congress determined
that no extension should be given for the protection of these works (although
Congress did extend by 20 years, to 2047,[66]
the “extra” protection granted to such works as an inducement to get them
published by the end of 2002). Thus, thousands, or millions, of unpublished
works, including private letters dating back to the early history of the United
States, will first go into the public domain after December 31, 2002,
demonstrating Congress’s sensitivity to the value of the public domain.
As with the 1976 term extension,
Congress was concerned that the authors or their heirs, rather than the
copyright licensees, be the ones to receive the benefit of the 20 year term
extension. Accordingly, Congress provided a new termination right in section
304(d) for authors or heirs who did not previously take advantage of the
termination provided in section 304(c).
Congress did not provide, either in
1976 or in 1998, for a termination right in works made for hire. However, in
the CTEA, Congress did take the extraordinary step of adopting a sense of
Congress that owners of audiovisual works should make arrangements to share the
value of the additional 20-year extension with those who participated in the
creation of the works. Section 105 of the CTEA provides:
It is the sense of the Congress that copyright owners of
audiovisual works for which the term of copyright protection is extended by the
amendments made by this title, and the screenwriters, directors, and performers
of those audiovisual works, should negotiate in good faith in an effort to
reach a voluntary agreement or voluntary agreements with respect to the
establishing of a fund or other mechanism for the amount of remuneration to be
divided among the parties for the exploitation of those audiovisual works.
Although
this sense of Congress does not have the force of law, it presumably puts the
industry on notice that, should such negotiations not be forthcoming, Congress
might consider enacting legislation to force the copyright owners to share the
benefits of the copyright term extension (assuming, of course, that the Supreme
Court doesn’t bar Congress from making ongoing adjustments to existing rights
of copyright).
Thus, it is clear that Congress in
the 1998 legislation continued doing what it has been doing for the full 212
years of copyright in this country, promoting the “Progress of Science and
useful Arts” by carefully balancing the interests of copyright owners and
copyright users.
d. Copyright
Balances
In their amicus brief filed with the
Supreme Court petitioning for certiorari, the law professors in support of the
petitioners speculated about the impact the appellate court's ruling might have
on the Digital Millennium Copyright Act, the restoration of foreign copyrights
under section 104A, various other recent enactments, and potential enactments that
have not yet even been considered by Congress. The professors were concerned
about the impact on court interpretations of the DMCA, particularly involving
potential idea/expression and fair use arguments. The law professors did not
stress the point in their filing on the merits, and I did not include the
following analysis in my own amicus brief.
In
deciding whether the CTEA is constitutional or not, the Supreme Court must make
an all-or-nothing choice. Congress, on the other hand, is the proper body for
weighing competing considerations and coming up with a "compromise"
that protects the interests of all parties. That's exactly what it did in the
CTEA when it expanded the library exemption during the added 20 year term, and
when it limited the scope of the musical performance right by various
amendments placing restrictions on performing rights societies.
In
the future, Congress might adopt any number of other "compromises" to
assure the continued "Progress of Science and useful Arts." Congress
might conclude that the longer term is not appropriate for some categories of
works, and adopt a shorter term for such works as works of applied art, as is
allowed under the Berne Convention. If Congress is concerned about the
availability of older works that are still the subject of copyright, it might
adopt a compulsory license to cover the situation, much as it provided for a
compulsory license for the continued use of derivative works by "reliance
parties" based upon works whose copyright was restored under §104A.[67]
For example, the Connecticut statute of 1783 provided that, if an author
"shall neglect to furnish the public with sufficient editions thereof, or
shall sell the same at a price unreasonable," then a court was empowered
to grant a complainant "a full and ample licence to re-print and publish
such book, pamphlet, map or chart, in such numbers and for such term as said
court shall judge just and reasonable."
I
don't advocate such a compromise, but the fact remains that there are plenty of
ways, short of judicially throwing works into the public domain, to protect any
legitimate copyright user and First Amendment concerns. The copyright laws do not raise such constitutional concerns
as they currently exist, precisely because Congress and the courts have seen fit to impose the
idea/expression, fair use, compulsory license, and other limitations on the
rights of copyright. It is not necessary or appropriate to speculate whether
any future copyright law, no matter how absurd, might be unconstitutional. The
only issue is whether Congress, in passing the law it did, acted within its
constitutional authority, including promoting the "Progress of Science and
useful Arts," properly understood to incorporate a wide range of concerns.
That is precisely the role that Congress is situated to play, and that is
presumably the reason that the Constitution grants Congress the power to set
the parameters of copyright law.
The
reason I cut this argument from my amicus brief was that it might have seemed
to suggest that there was some less drastic alternative that Congress could
have passed, such as ones containing the above contemplated compulsory license,
and that the Supreme Court should declare the law unconstitutional until
Congress adopts the balance that the Court deems preferable. But if there are
less drastic alternatives, or if there are other ways of promoting the
legitimate interests of the "public domain," by compulsory licenses
or other devices, then we should all go back to Congress and discuss those
suggestions. The public domain literature has certainly served its purpose of
highlighting concerns that may not have been adequately voiced before, and for
that reason much of the literature does make a valuable contribution, despite
my criticisms here and elsewhere. I don't think that it would be appropriate,
however, for the Supreme Court to make the ultimately legislative decision
about what compulsory licenses or limiting doctrines should be adopted in each
context.
4. The Briefs—Conclusion
The copyright act is a series of
compromises and balances among competing interests. It would be unfair, and
perhaps impossible, to unravel one part of this act without upsetting the
careful balance that only Congress is in a position to achieve. The point was
well made by Ralph Oman, former Register of Copyrights, in a letter to the
editor of the Washington Post on
March 11, 2002:
During the
past 90 years, to solve political controversies and to hand out economic
freebies to sympathetic supplicants, Congress has sweet-talked authors into
giving up their right to say yes or no to a use of their works—the essence of a
property right—in exchange for a longer term. A long list of special pleaders
now gets free use of copyrighted works, including small businesses, veterans' groups,
bars, scholars, restaurants, fraternal groups, marching bands, Boy Scout
troops, nursing homes, libraries, radio broadcasters and home tapers. Another
long list of powerful industries gets to use copyrighted works in exchange for
a small government-set fee, whether the author likes it or not: cable and
satellite companies, record companies, juke-box operators, public broadcasters
and, most recently, Internet companies.
The authors
went along with this coerced subsidization because Congress held out the
promise of a longer term of protection. It would be a switch-a-roo worthy of
Lucy yanking away Charlie Brown's football if the Supreme Court removed the
carrot and left the authors with the dirty end of the stick.
C.
Rebuttal
There are several misrepresentations
or mischaracerizations in the petitioners' presentation of the case. Most of
what follows are responses I make in the footnotes of my amicus brief.
1. The Number of Copyright Extensions
Petitioners state throughout their
brief that Congress has extended the term of copyright “eleven times in the
past forty years.” This is a statement that also appears throughout Lawrence
Lessig's most recent book,[68]
and that many public domain advocates seem to enjoy repeating. These statements
are misleading, if not downright disingenuous. In the past 90 years (since the
1909 act established a maximum duration of 56 years), the term has been
basically extended only twice, to life plus 50 years in 1978, and to life plus
70 years in 1998. The other nine extensions were interim extensions for roughly
one- or two-year periods, enacted between 1962 and 1974,[69]
so that copyrighted works would not go into the public domain pending adoption
of the new 75-year term for existing copyrights. In no case did the extension
exceed the 75-year term that was ultimately adopted by Congress in the 1976
Act.
Congress has hardly been headstrong
in extending the term of copyright. In 1909 and throughout the twentieth
century, many advocates of copyright proposed rejection of the “outmoded”
structure of the Statute of Anne, and adoption of the life plus 50 year system
that prevailed in most of the rest of the world. Had Congress adopted the more
modern term in 1909, instead of 1976, there would have been only two term extensions
in the last 170 years (since the extension to a maximum of 42 years in 1831),
instead of the last 90 years.
2. The Belittling of International
Considerations
In his book, The Future of Ideas, Lawrence Lessig explains the
"repeated" extensions of copyright as being a power-grabbing ploy of
the giant corporations. At various websites on the Eldred case, the slogan "Free the Mouse" is prominently
displayed,[70] and public
domain advocates seem to enjoy calling the CTEA the "Mickey Mouse"
act. In his book, Lessig pretty much dismisses the international considerations
that were at the heart of copyright term extension.[71]
The briefs also belittle the international considerations.
Some of the public domain literature
argues that the international considerations are irrelevant to the issue, since
the rest of the world obviously is not subject to the United States
Constitution, as is Congress. However, although the laws of other countries may
reflect different cultures and different histories, it is nevertheless
instructive to consider how other nations have set about dealing with common
problems of enforcing copyright in an emerging global technology. As stated by
Justice Breyer in Printz v. U.S.,
Of
course, we are interpreting our own Constitution, not those of other nations,
and there may be relevant political and structural differences between their
systems and our own. . . . But their experience may nonetheless cast an
empirical light on the consequences of different solutions to a common legal
problem . . . [72]
3. The Arguments Against
"Harmonization"
It is true that the adoption of the
CTEA did not result in complete "harmonization" with foreign
copyright laws. A lot of the “disharmony” that petitioners and several amici
observe results from measuring new copyrights from the date of the author’s
death, and measuring old, and some new, copyrights from the date of
publication. Petitioners try to make much of the inevitable disparity. For
example, they state at p. 3 that “As applied to an author who produced
throughout a long lifetime in the pattern of Irving Berlin, the current rule
would produce a term of 140 years.” The statement is misleading. The 140 year
term would apply only to Berlin’s early works; works produced shortly before
his death would endure only for a little over 70 years under the CTEA. In any
event, most of the "disharmonies," both between the laws of different
countries and internally within U.S. law, result from other decisions made
about other aspects of copyright, such as the treatment of works for hire. If
there are problems in the nonuniform treatment of those aspects, then those
aspects should be addressed separately.
4. The Stationers' Company Acts
Several briefs in favor of
petitioners link the Statute of Anne to the prior history of monopolies under
the Stationers’ Companies licensing acts. About this linkage, I refer to my
book:[73]
Some modern critics of the expansion
of copyright delight in emphasizing the embarrassing precursor to the Statute
of Anne, suggesting that copyright has been forever tainted by the fact that it
evolved from what were essentially censorship laws. However, there was a
critical gap in protection, from 1694 through 1710, and the new Statute of Anne
was not simply an extension of the previous law. Parliament seems not to have
been guided by the complaints of the publishers, who in 1709 had lobbied for a
return to the old licensing acts. Instead, they were obviously influenced by
the pleas of several famous authors for the recognition of rights not of
printers, but of authors. . . .
One way of putting the Stationers’
Licensing Acts into perspective is to realize that they were not the spiritual
precursors to copyright at all. However, because the crown and the publishers
had found a way to protect the rights of publishers, and the publishers were
accordingly willing to pay authors for their creations, a satisfactory solution
had been worked out that eased the pressure for a more direct copyright law to
protect authors. Once the stopgap measure was removed, the need for the
protection of authors’ rights came to the fore.
5. Quotes Supporting Short Copyright Terms
It's not hard to find quotations in
the public discourse that advocate a shorter term of copyright. As stated in
the reports to accompany the 1976 Act,[74]
“The debate over how long a copyright should last is as old as the oldest
copyright statute and will doubtless continue as long as there is a copyright
law.” The petitioners and their amici supply dozens of quotes from one side of
this debate to create the impression that there was general consensus on the
shortest possible copyright term. One can only marvel at the audacity of Profs.
Ochoa et al., who attach to their brief a 7-page appendix of an anonymous
letter strenuously advocating one side of this debate almost 300 years ago. The
“consensus” that actually developed over the years in this country, in England,
and throughout the European Union is a copyright term of life plus 70 years.
6. The Relevance of the Internet
Although the issue before the
Supreme Court does not directly involve the Internet or other new technologies,
petitioners and several amici in favor of petitioners suggest that their
interests are allied with the Internet, and that a decision against them will
somehow inhibit the development of this new technology. At pp. 5-6 of their
brief, for example, petitioners suggest that Eldred’s website is simply the
Internet equivalent of a public library, and that he should be entitled to some
online equivalent of the first sale doctrine
If Eldred wants to “compile” a
“collection” of Robert Frost books, he is perfectly free to do so under the
first sale doctrine. But if petitioners think that posting HTML versions of
those works on their Internet website is or should be the online equivalent of
the Derry New Hampshire Public Library’s lending of a particular copy to
members of their community, then they are fundamentally wrong. The Derry
library maintains individual copies of their books; when they are lent out,
they are unavailable to others. Works that are “posted” on the Internet, on the
other hand, can be viewed simultaneously by hundreds or thousands of users,
copied instantaneously to their computers, and redistributed in multiple copies
around the world. As demonstrated by the Audio Home Recording Act of 1992, the
Digital Performance Rights in Sound Recordings Act of 1995, and the Digital
Millennium Copyright Act of 1998, the proper Congressional response to the
digitization and posting of works is not a blanket exemption, but a careful
balancing of interests. Even with the first sale doctrine, libraries are also
subject to the elaborate provisions of section 108 to ensure that their copies
are not systematically used to make copies of works.
If petitioners want a “first sale”
equivalent for the Internet, they’ll have to convince Congress of its
advisability. Their ability or inability to get a special exemption during the
life of a particular copyright, however, should have nothing to do with the
issue before the Supreme Court: whether Congress acted within its
constitutional authority when it extended the duration of copyright in the
CTEA.
Petitioners argue that their view of
the public domain is made more urgent by the development of new markets for
creative works, particularly the Internet. The response by Congress to the
development of new markets, however—particularly new technologies for
exploiting copyright works—is generally to give the copyright owners or the
original creators or their heirs an opportunity to get some benefit from that
new market. Sometimes this is achieved through a compulsory license, such as
the compulsory license provided in the Audio Home Recording Act of 1992.
Sometimes it is achieved by creating new rights, such as was provided in the
Digital Performance Rights in Sound Recordings Act of 1995.[75]
7. Copyright's "Quid Pro Quo"
Petitioners recognize at p. 23 of
their brief the “quid pro quo requirement of the copyright clause.” Under
copyright law from 1790 through 1977, publication was generally the
prerequisite for federal copyright. Since 1978, the only requirement has been
“fixation” of an original work “in a tangible medium of expression.”[79]
Even though copyrighted works are thus protected from the date of their
creation, it is the genius of the copyright system that copyright owners only
profit by making their works available to others, so they (and their
publishers) still have an incentive to publish. Thus, while the particular
expression may be protected, the ideas and facts and other noncopyrightable
aspects of the works are made available to the public, as described at p.__, supra.
The “quid pro quo” is for the
volitional acts of creating and publishing works. If part of the social
“contract” is that works ultimately go into the public domain, then that aspect
of the “bargain” is something of an adhesion contract for the authors. They
have no choice whether or when their work goes into the public domain, and can
hardly be said to have acquiesced to any particular duration for protection of
their works.
8. Mischaracterization of Effect of
Automatic Renewal
Petitioners argue at page 7, and
repeat in fn. 13 on p. 30, that the problems they associate with the copyright
term extension are compounded by the fact that “renewal” has been “automatic”
since 1992. They argue that 375,000 copyrights have been “blocked” in order to
“protect” 77,000 commercially viable works. They then argue that “under current
law,” as a result of automatic renewal, “3.35 million works would be blocked to
protect 77,000.” That is a mischaracterization of the effects of the law. The
1992 amendment that made renewal automatic applies to works that were created
between 1964 and 1977, inclusive. The only works created between 1923 and 1963
that were still under copyright, and therefore subject to the 1998 term
extension, were those that were in fact renewed by the copyright owners. Those
works published between 1923 and 1963 that were not registered for renewal have
already gone into the public domain, and are not extended by the 1998 act.
9. Mischaracterization of Fair Use Cases
The petitioners’
intellectual property law professors’ brief states at p. 26 that “One of the
most troubling aspects of copyright in recent years is that the limitations on
copyright liability, including the idea-expression distinction and fair use,
have been steadily shrinking via judicial construction . . . .” This statement
is absolutely wrong. The Supreme Court’s clarification of the wide scope of
fair use in a parody context, Campbell v.
Acuff-Rose Music, Inc.,[80] has been embraced by the lower courts.[81]
In the context of new technologies, the Supreme Court held in Sony Corp. of America v. Universal City
Studios, Inc.,[82] that
fair use included the “time-shifting” of television programs through the use of
home video recorders. The Supreme Court’s holding in Feist Publications, Inc. v. Rural Telephone Service Co., Inc.,[83]
while not an “idea/expression” case, was founded upon the related
fact/expression distinction. Computer
Associates International, Inc. v. Altai, Inc.[84]and
similar cases have resulted in a “thin” copyright for computer programs, based
upon concepts related to the idea/expression distinction and the works of
utility doctrine. The holding in Recording
Ind. Ass’n of America v. Diamond Multimedia Systems, Inc.[85] that the Digital Millennium Copyright
Act does not apply to the popular RIO MP3 music player, while decided on the
technicalities of that statute, was a major victory in what might be considered
a fair use context. It’s hard to imagine how the copyright law professors can
conclude that the basic limitations of copyright have not been doing their
historical job of balancing the rights of copyright owners and users.
10. Economic Efficiency Analysis
a. The Economists' Brief
The petitioners’ economists’ brief
begins with the statement, at p. 2: “One possibility is that Congress sought a
policy that confers a net economic benefit, after subtracting the expected
costs.” This is a pretty lame statement, since it sets up the entire brief as
based upon a policy that it doesn't even say Congress adopted.
Despite the attempts by some
scholars to test all copyrights on the Procrustean bed of economic efficiency
analysis, Congress has simply never limited itself to such an approach. The
moral rights provided in section 106A, the termination rights of sections 203
and 304(c), and dozens of other rights and limitations don’t lend themselves to
economic evaluation. As concluded by the leading copyright scholar today, the
utilitarian approach does not explain many of the recent copyright amendments.[86]
One of the basic problems with an
efficiency analysis of copyright is that many of the variables involved in the
copyright industries simply are not quantifiable. For example, in making the
argument that increased revenues for the copyright industries will not result
in any greater investment in future works, the economists blithely suggest at
p. 9 of their brief that “In general, a profit-maximizing producer should fund
the set of projects that have an expected return equal to or greater than their
cost of capital.” One is reminded of the proverbial critic who, upon being told
that only one out of ten movies makes money, responded, “Then only invest in
the ones that make money.” Of course, if one knew in advance which
multimillion-dollar movies would be successful, one would have no difficulty
making money.
The fact is that the copyright
industries are based upon products that usually have, at the outset, an
undeterminable value. One book sells, another doesn’t; one movie is
a blockbuster, the other a disaster. If one were to do an economic
analysis, one would probably conclude that, given the unlikelihood of success,
it is hardly ever worth publishing a book or producing a play or a movie. It is
precisely because the chance of success is so small that we have to make the
reward for success great. The copyright industries are made up, to a large
extent, of what the economists call “sub-par projects,” and it would be a mistake
to leave to the economists the choice of which works to subsidize.
b. The
Petitioners' Brief
Petitioners at p. 7 make an argument
similar to that contained in the economists’ brief, that the “cost” to society
of “withholding” lots of copyrighted works exceeds the “gain” to be realized by
those few copyright holders who have “surviving works” (defined by petitioners
as “works that continue to earn a royalty”). The argument is fallacious.
The petitioners effectively divide
all works into two categories, those that have commercial viability, and those
that don’t. For those that don’t have commercial viability after dozens of
years—the vast majority of works—there really isn’t much “cost” in tying them
up in copyright or otherwise. We might as well leave them in the control of
people who have a sentimental or other noncommercial interest in them, since
such people are more likely to preserve or disseminate the works. The works
that second-comers are most interested in reproducing, however, are precisely
the same “surviving works” that have commercial viability to the original
creators or their heirs. Assuming that a given work has some remaining
commercial viability, then, it is a worthwhile question to ask: is it more
“fair” to grant whatever value there may be to the creators, their heirs, or
the company that absorbed the initial cost and took the initial risk in
creating the work, or to pass the remaining commercial value to the free-rider
who waits until a work’s commercial success is proven, and then jumps in to
take advantage? But, of course, economic analysis doesn’t factor in what is
“fair.” Maybe that’s why Congress doesn’t particularly limit itself to economic
analysis in deciding who should control the further dissemination of creative works.
Many or most of the works that
petitioners want to distribute are of course the “successful” works that are
already available to the public. For example, Kahlil Gibran’s The Prophet, which, we are told, at p. 3
of petitioners’ brief, Dover anxiously wants to publish, is already available
in many editions, including a new hardcover copy on amazon.com for $10.50, or a
paperback edition for $5.95. Some works are indeed out of print in this
country; petitioners’ intellectual property law professors’ brief highlights
the out of print status of H. G. Wells’s 1933 novel, The Shape of Things to Come. However, they seem not to appreciate
the ease with which copies even of out-of-print books can be obtained in the
days of the Internet. Amazon U.K. lists a paperback edition for Ł4.79. Under
the Supreme Court’s ruling in Quality
King Distributors, Inc. v. L’anza Research International, Inc.,[87]
it is not a violation of anyone’s copyright to order individual copies of
copyrighted works from other countries.
Indeed, under the first sale
doctrine, copies of works that have been legitimately sold in this country may
be resold, and even out-of-print works may be obtained at specialty sites such
as abe.com (“Advanced Book Exchange”). As of the middle of June, abe.com listed
95 available copies of The Shape of
Things to Come, including some for as little as $7, and 45 from U.S.
sources for as little as $10.
11. Congressional Hearings
At p. 3 of their amicus brief,
petitioners' law professors quote the Register of Copyrights suggesting that
anti-copyright forces may not have shown up at the Copyright Office hearings of
1993, perhaps because "legislation did not appear on the horizon."
The implication of the quote is that somehow the bill slipped its way through
the legislative process without a complete review of the issues. By the time
the bill was reported to Congress, however, it had been given a very complete
review, totaling over 1000 pages of statements and appendices presented in
hearings. The Senate Judiciary Committee held hearings in 1995 solely on the
issue of term extension.[88]
The House Judiciary Committee's Subcommittee on Courts and Intellectual
Property held hearings in 1995 in Los Angeles, Washington, D.C, Nashville, and
online.[89]
Many of the same law professors who participated in the preparation of the
brief also presented a statement opposing term extension; and the Senate Report
contained minority views. The minority views of Senator Brown extensively
recite some of the same arguments presented in the Eldred case, so it can hardly be argued that Congress wasn't fully
informed of the opposition to term extension.
The various extensions of copyright
over the years, balanced by careful limitations on the rights of copyright
owners, are not the result of some nefarious scheme by corporations to cheat
the public of their rights. Rather, they are part of the remarkable system
envisioned by the framers of the Constitution, and implemented by the Congress
and the President, to "promote the Progress of Science and useful
Arts" by doing exactly what the Constitution says they are supposed to do,
"by securing, for limited Times, to Authors and Inventors, the exclusive
Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries." The Supreme Court
should not accept petitioners' novel theory that would limit Congress in its
ability to continue balancing the interests of copyright owners with the
interests of copyright users.
· Prof. of Law, New York Law School. Prof. Samuels's copyright website is at www.nyls.edu/samuels/copyright.
[1] Edward Samuels, The Public Domain in Copyright Law, 41 J. Copyright Soc'y 137 (1993) [hereinafter "The Public Domain"].
[2] Id. at 150.
[3] James Boyle, The Second Enclosure Movement and the Construction of the Public Domain, preliminary discussion draft for the Conference on the Public Domain at Duke Law School Nov. 9-11, 2001. http://www.law.duke.edu/pd/papers/boyle.pdf, at 38-43.
[4] Eldred v. Reno, 74 F. Supp. 2d 1 (D.D.C. 1999), aff'd, 239 F.3d 372 (D.C.Cir. 2001), reh'g denied, 255 F.3d 849 (2001), cert. granted sub nom. Eldred v. Ashcroft, __ U.S. __ (No. 01-618, 2002).
[5] Pub. L. No. 98-450, 98 Stat. 1727 (1984), amending 17 U.S.C. §109.
[6] Pub. L. No. 101-650, 104 Stat. 5134 (1990), amending 17 U.S.C. §109.
[7] Pub. L. No. 102-563, 106 Stat. 4237 (1992), adding 17 U.S.C., ch. 10.
[8] Pub. L. 104-39, 109 Stat. 336 (1995), adding 17 U.S.C. §106(6) and §114(d)-(j).
[9] Pub. L. No. 105-304, 112 Stat. 2863 (1998), adding, among other things, 17 U.S.C., ch. 12.
[10] Lawrence Lessig, The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World (2001).
[11] I've just finished reading the science fiction works, Hyperion and Fall of Hyperion, by Dan Simmons. Those works are somewhat more apocalyptic in their portrayal of the battle among the forces of the "Hegemony," the "Technocore," and the mysterious "Ousters." But Lessig's book certainly taps into a popular fear/fantasy of the tech-savvy citizens of the Internet.
[12] The Public Domain at 177-78 (extensive footnotes omitted).
[13] Black’s Law Dictionary defines “property” as “that which belongs exclusively to one”; and copyright is defined as a set of “exclusive rights” in §§106 and 106A. When it serves their interests, petitioners in the Eldred case are not averse to using a property law analogy. “Copyright law had, in effect, vested in these petitioners, as well as in the public, a remainderman interest in the works at stake.” Petitioners’ brief at 6. Of course, a remainderman is only “one who is entitled to the remainder of the estate after a particular estate carved out of it has expired.” Black’s Law Dictionary.
[14] See Paul Goldstein, Copyright's Highway: From Gutenberg to the Celestial Jukebox, ch. ___, "The Two Cultures of Copyright" (1995).
[15] Thorvald Solberg, Copyright Office Bulletin No. 3, Copyright Enactments of the United States 1783-1906 (1906) at 11 (Connecticut), 27 (Georgia), and 29 (New York).
[16] Id. at 14 (Massachusetts), 18 (New Hampshire), and 19 (Rhode Island).
[17] Id. at 25.
[18] Report of the Register of Copyrights on the General Revision of the U.S. Copyright Law 3-6 (1961).
[19]1 Paul Goldstein, Copyright, §1.1 at ___ (1989).
[20] Id. at 7.
[21] The Public Domain, at 180-83.
[22] The Public Domain, at 175.
[23] Id. at 175-76.
[24] 2 Sutherland Stat. Const. §41.05 (5th ed., Norman J. Singer 1992), at 368.
[25] While the primary import of §104A is to cover works that went into the public domain due to "noncompliance with formalities imposed at any time by United States copyright law, including failure of renewal, lack of proper notice, or failure to comply with any manufacturing requirements," the act also applies to foreign sound recordings published before the effective date of U.S. protection. 17 U.S.C. §104A((h)(6).
[26] No. 01-B-1854 (D. Colo., filed Sept. 19, 2001).
[27] For example, some countries didn't grant rights in sound recordings or computer programs until relatively late in the twentieth century, and sound recordings and computer programs represented substantial U.S. exports.
[28] "Retroactive" is probably the wrong word to use here. Even §104A doesn't apply to activities that took place before it was passed. It restores copyrights, but only applies to activities that take place after its enactment. Indeed, it contains an elaborate mechanism for protecting "reliance parties" who may have invested in what they thought were public domain works. These mechanisms involve notice of intent to restore copyright, and even a compulsory license at a reasonable compensation for creators of derivative works based upon works that were, at the time, in the public domain. 17 U.S.C. §104A(d)(3).
[29] 82 F. Supp. 2d 211 (S.D.N.Y. 2000).
[30] 273 F.3d 429 (2d Cir. 2001).
[31] Although several amici take a different
position, petitioners concede at p. 14 of their brief that Congress is the
proper body to determine the duration of copyright: “Whether 50 years is
enough, or 70 years too much, is not a judgment meet for this Court.”
Petitioners’ entire constitutional attack is directed at the application of the
CTEA to existing works; their only argument against the application of the CTEA
to works created after its effective date is that the different applications of
the statute are inseverable. Id. at
48.
I find the concession remarkable. It also reintroduces the very same issue that was decided by the D.C. Circuit, but that the Supreme Court specifically declined to hear: the extent to which courts may consider arguments raised by amici that are not raised, or are conceded, by the parties to the action.
[32] Berne Convention Implementation Act of 1988, Pub. L. No. 100-568, 102 Stat. 2853.
[33] Pub. L. No. 102-307, 106 Stat. 264 (1992), amending 17 U.S.C. §304(a).
[34] Harper & Row Pubs., Inc. v. Nation Enterprises, 471 U.S. 539 (1985).
[35] Pub. L. No. 105-298, 112 Stat. 2831 (1998).
[36] Petitioners' brief at 13.
[37] The Federalist No. 43, at 279 (Mod. Lib. ed. 1941).
[38] Statute of Anne, (8 Anne c. 19, 1710).
[39] http://www.nobel.se/nobel/nobel-foundation/statutes.html.
[40] 510 U.S. 569 (1994).
[41] 268 F.3d 1257 (2001)
[42] Thorvald Solberg, Copyright Office Bulletin No. 8, Copyright in Congress 1789-1904 (1905, reprinted 1976), at 115-16.
[43] Id. at 118.
[44] Actually, the statutes of Pennsylvania and Maryland provided that they would not apply until copyright statutes had been adopted in all 13 states, so presumably copyright was inoperative in those states because Delaware never adopted a copyright law. Additionally, the statutes of Connecticut, Massachusetts, New Hampshire, Rhode Island, North Carolina, and New York provided that copyright would not extend to works created by authors from other states unless those other states adopted their own copyright laws. See generally Thorvald Solberg, Copyright Office Bulletin No. 3, Copyright Enactments of the United States 1783-1906 (1906). So even in these states, works by citizens of other states may have gone into the public domain when they were published.
[45] Act of May 31, 1790, 1 Stat. 124, §1.
[46] 4 Stat. 436 (1831).
[47] 17 U.S.C. §24 (1909) (repealed 1978).
[48] The 1976 Act provided that anonymous works, pseudonymous works, and works made for hire would be protected for 75 years from publication, or 100 years from the date of creation, whichever expired first. The CTEA provides that such works are protected for 95 years from publication or 120 years from creation, whichever expires first. Petitioners can hardly complain about the 100- or 120-year periods from the date of creation, since those terms are much shorter than the rights “in perpetuity” that applied to unpublished works from 1790 through 1977. See this section, infra.
[49] 17 U.S.C. § 111.
[50] 17 U.S.C. §106(5).
[51] 17 U.S.C. §106A.
[52] 17 U.S.C. §106(6).
[53] Berne Article 5(2).
[54] See generally Edward Samuels, The Illustrated Story of Copyright 230-48 (2000).
[55] Berne Article 7(1).
[56] Berne Article 5(2).
[57] There is a limited exception in Article 18(2), which provides that "If, however, through the expiry of the term of protection which was previously granted, a work has fallen into the public domain of the country where protection is claimed, that work shall not be protected anew." In addition, under Article 18(3), there is some room for member countries to determine "the conditions of application of this principle." There was a vigorous debate at the time of U.S. adherence to Berne whether Article 18 required the United States to "restore" copyright in works that had gone into the public domain as the result of a failure to meet the notice and registration formalities. See Final Report of the Ad Hoc Working Group on U.S. Adherence to the Berne Convention 75, republished in 10 Columbia-VLA Journal of Law & the Arts 511, 587 (1986). A consensus developed that the United States didn't necessarily have to restore such works. While Article 18 arguably allowed the United States not to restore works that had fallen into the public domain because of a failure of copyright formalities, the term extension for existing works still under copyright protection was an absolute necessity for joining Berne. We were apparently able under subsection (3) to determine that we would comply with Article 18 by granting a fixed term of 75 years to existing copyrights (on average the equivalent of life plus 50). There was at least some argument that the 75 year term in some cases yielded less than the life plus 50 year term required by Berne; the life plus 70 year term of the CTEA thus shored up United States law against any challenge based upon this argument.
[58] Cf. The Federalist, No. 43 at 279 (Mod. Lib. ed. 1941).
[59] Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enterprises, 471 U.S. 539, ___ (1985)
[60] 17 U.S.C. §101, definition of “pictorial, graphic and sculptural works."
[61] 17 U.S.C. §109.
[62] 17 U.S.C. §105.
[63] 17 U.S.C. §102.
[64] 17 U.S.C. §108.
[65] S. Rep. No. 104-315, 104th Cong., 2d Sess., to accompany S. 483 (1996) at 5-6.
[66] Amending 17 U.S.C. §303.
[67] See p. __, supra.
[68] Lawrence Lessig, The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World (2001).
[69] Pub. L. 87-668, 76 Stat. 555 (1962); Pub. L. 89-142, 79 Stat. 581 (1965); Pub. L. 90-141, 81 Stat. 464 (1967); Pub. L. 90-416, 82 Stat. 397 (1968); Pub. L.91-147, 83 Stat. 360 (1969); Pub. L. 91-555, 84 Stat. 1441 (1970); Pub. L. 92-170, 85 Stat. 490 (1971); Pub. L. 92-566, 86 Stat. 1181 (1972), Pub. L. 93-573, 88 Stat. 1873 (1974)
[70] The slogan used to be accompanied by a stylized "logo" looking like Mickey Mouse with lines through it, but they've recently dropped that logo.
[71] One of Lessig's proposals is that the United States adopt a copyright system of five-year terms subject to renewals. In a footnote, Lessig concedes that "Some of the changes I propose here would require changes to or the abrogation of some treaties," particularly the Berne Convention, the TRIPS/WTO agreement, and the two WIPO treaties. But to "change or abrogate" major international copyright law is hardly a simple matter, and could cause untold hardships to some American copyright industries.
[72] 521 U.S. 898, 977 (dissent) (1977) (in the context of the Brady Act).
[73] Edward Samuels, The Illustrated Story of Copyright (2000) at 16-17.
[74] S. Rep. No. 94-473, 94th Cong., 1st Sess. (1975), at 133; H.R. Rep. No. 94-1476, 94th Cong., 2d Sess. (1976).
[75] And sometimes Congress chooses not to extend the rights of existing parties to new technologies. For example, the Sound Recording Amendment of 1971 applied only to recordings made after its effective date in 1972, and did not create rights in recordings already made.
[76] 17 U.S.C. §1006(b).
[77] 17 U.S.C. §114(g).
[78]
As stated in S. Rep. No. 315, 104th Cong., 2d Sess, (1966), at 6:
[U]nprecedented growth
in technology, including the advent of digital media and the development of the
National Information Infrastructure (NII) and the Global Information
Infrastructure (GII), have dramatically increased incentives to preserve
existing works.
As recited at p. 12 of that report, the Register
of Copyrights noted before the Committee in 1995:
Technological developments clearly have extended the commercial life of copyrighted works. Examples include video cassettes, which have given new life to movies and television series, expanded cable television, satellite delivery, which promise [sic] up to 500 channels thereby creating a demand for content, the advent of multimedia, which also is creating a demand for content, and international networks such as Internet, i.e., the global information highway. The question is who should benefit from these increased commercial uses?
[79] 17 U.S.C. §102(a).
[80] 510 U.S. 569 (1994).
[81] See, e.g., Leibovitz v. Paramount Pictures Corp., 137 F. 3d 109 (2d Cir. 1998) and Suntrust Bank v. Houghton Mifflin Co., 268 F.3d 1257 (11th Cir. 2001).
[82] 464 U.S. 417 (1984).
[83] 499 U.S. 340 (1991).
[84] 982 F.2d 693 (2nd Cir. 1992).
[85] 180 F.3d 1072 (9th Cir. 1999).
[86] See Paul Goldstein, supra note ___.
[87] 523 U.S. 135 (1998).
[88] Hearing Before the Committee on the Judiciary, Unites States Senate, 104th Cong., 1st Sess., on S. 483, Sept. 20, 1995, Serial No. J-104-46 (USGPO 1997).
[89] Hearings Before the Subcommittee on Courts and Intellectual Property of the Committee on the Judiciary, House of Representatives, 104th Cong., 1st Sess., on H.R. 989, H.R. 1248, and H.R. 1734, Copyright Term, Film Labeling, and Film Preservation Legislation, June 1 & July 13, 1995, Serial No. 53 (H521-36) (USGPO 1996); Hearing Before the Subcommittee on Courts and Intellectual Property of the Committee on the Judiciary, House of Representatives, 105th Cong., 1st Sess., Pre-1978 Distribution of Recordings Containing Musical Compositions; Copyright Term Extension; and Copyright per Program Licenses, June 27, 1997, Serial No. 39 (43-666 CC) (USGPO 1997).